READING HALLTHE DOORS OF WISDOM |
GEORGE GROTE'S HISTORY OF GREECE CHAPTER
XXXI.
GRECIAN
AFFAIRS AFTER THE EXPULSION OF THE PEISISTRATIDS.— REVOLUTION OF CLEISTHENES
AND ESTABLISHMENT OF DEMOCRACY AT ATHENS.
With Hippias disappeared the mercenary
Thracian garrison, upon which he and his father before him had leaned for
defense as well as for enforcement of authority. Cleomenes with his
Lacedaemonian forces retired also, after staying only long enough to establish
a personal friendship, productive subsequently of important consequences
between the Spartan king and the Athenian Isagoras. The Athenians were thus
left to themselves, without any foreign interference to constrain them in
their political arrangements.
It
has been mentioned in the preceding chapter, that the Peisistratids had for the most part respected the forms of the Solonian constitution. The
nine archons, and the probouleutic or preconsidering Senate of Four Hundred (both annually
changed), still continued to subsist, together with occasional meetings of the
people—or rather of such portion of the people as was comprised in the gentes, phratries, and four Ionic tribes. The
timocratic classification of Solon (or quadruple scale of income and
admeasurement of political franchises according to it) also continued to
subsist—but all within the tether and subservient to the purposes of the ruling
family, who always kept one of their number as real master among the chief
administrators, and always retained possession of the acropolis as well as of
the mercenary force.
That
overawing pressure being now removed by the expulsion of Hippias, the enslaved
forms became at once endued with freedom and reality. There appeared again,
what Attica had not known for thirty years, declared political parties, and
pronounced opposition, between two men as leaders—on one side, Isagoras, son of Tisander, a person of illustrious descent—on the
other, Cleisthenes, the Alcmaeonid, not less illustrious, and possessing at
this moment a claim on the gratitude of his countrymen as the most persevering
as well as the most effective foe of the dethroned despots. In what manner such
opposition was carried on we are not told. It would seem to have been not
altogether pacific; but at any rate, Cleisthenes had the worst of it, and in
consequence of his defeat (says the historian) “he took into partnership the
people, who had been before excluded from everything”. His
partnership with the people gave birth to the Athenian democracy; it was a real
and important revolution.
DEMOCRATICAL
REVOLUTION.
The
political franchise, or the character of an Athenian citizen, both before and
since Solon, had been confined to the primitive four Ionic tribes, each of
which was an aggregate of so many close corporations or quasi-families—the gentes and the phratries. None of the
residents in Attica, therefore, except those included in some gens or phratry,
had any part in the political franchise. Such non-privileged residents were
probably at all times numerous, and became more and more so by means of fresh
settlers. Moreover they tended most to multiply in Athens and Peiraeus, where
immigrants would commonly establish themselves. Cleisthenes, breaking down the
existing wall of privilege, imparted the political franchise to the excluded
mass. But this could not be done by enrolling them in new gentes or phratries, created in addition to the old. For the gentile tie was
founded upon old faith and feeling which in the existing state of the Greek
mind could not be suddenly conjured up as a bond of union for comparative
strangers. It could only be done by disconnecting the franchise altogether from
the Ionic tribes as well as from the gentes which constituted them, and by redistributing the population into new tribes
with a character and purpose exclusively political. Accordingly Cleisthenes
abolished the four Ionic tribes, and created in their place ten new tribes
founded upon a different principle, independent of the gentes and phratries. Each of his new tribes comprised a certain number of
demes or cantons, with the enrolled proprietors and residents in each of them.
The demes taken altogether included the entire surface of Attica, so that the Cleisthenean
constitution admitted to the political franchise all the free native Athenians;
and not merely these, but also many metics, and even
some of the superior order of slaves. Putting out of sight the general body of
slaves, and regarding only the free inhabitants, it was in point of fact a
scheme approaching to universal suffrage, both political and judicial.
The
slight and cursory manner in which Herodotus announces this memorable
revolution tends to make us overlook its real importance. He dwells chiefly on
the alteration in the number and names of the tribes; Cleisthenes, he says,
despised the Ionians so much, that he would not tolerate the continuance in
Attica of the four tribes which prevailed in the Ionic cities; deriving their
names from the four sons of Ion—just as his grandfather, the Sicyonian Cleisthenes, hating the Dorians, had degraded and
nicknamed the three Dorian tribes at Sicyon. Such is the representation of
Herodotus, who seems himself to have entertained some contempt for the Ionians,
and therefore to have suspected a similar feeling where it had no real
existence.
But
the scope of Cleisthenes was something far more extensive. He abolished the
four ancient tribes, not because they were Ionic, but because
they had become incommensurate with the existing condition of the Attic
people, and because such abolition procured both for himself and for his
political scheme new as well as hearty allies. And, indeed, if we study the circumstances
of the case, we shall see very obvious reasons to suggest the proceeding. For
more than thirty years—an entire generation—the old constitution had been a
mere empty formality, working only in subservience to the reigning dynasty, and
stripped of all real controlling power. We may be very sure, therefore, that
both the Senate of Four Hundred and the popular assembly, divested of that free
speech which imparted to them not only all their value but all their charm, had
come to be of little public estimation, and were probably attended only by a
few partisans. Under such circumstances, the difference between qualified
citizens and men not so qualified—between members of the four old tribes and
men not members—became during this period practically effaced. This in fact
was the only species of good which a Grecian despotism ever seems to have done.
It confounded the privileged and the non-privileged under one coercive
authority common to both, so that the distinction between the two was not easy
to revive when the despotism passed away. As soon as Hippias was expelled, the
senate and the public assembly regained their efficiency; but had they been
continued on the old footing, including none but members of the four tribes,
these tribes would have been re-invested with a privilege which in reality they
had so long lost, that its revival would have seemed an odious novelty, and the
remaining population would probably not have submitted to it. If in addition we
consider the political excitement of the moment—the restoration of one body of
men from exile, and the departure of another body into exile—the outpouring of
long-suppressed hatred, partly against these very forms by the corruption of
which the despot had reigned—we shall see that prudence as well as patriotism
dictated the adoption of an enlarged scheme of government. Cleisthenes had
learnt some wisdom during his long exile; and as he probably continued for some
time after the introduction of his new constitution, to be the chief adviser of
his countrymen, we may consider their extraordinary success as a testimony to
his prudence and skill not less than to their courage and unanimity.
NAMES
OF THE TRIBES.
Nor
does it seem unreasonable to give him credit for a more generous forward
movement than what is implied in the literal account of Herodotus. Instead of
being forced against his will to purchase popular support by proposing this new
constitution, Cleisthenes may have proposed it before, during the discussions
which immediately followed the retirement of Hippias; so that the rejection of
it formed the ground of quarrel (and no other ground is mentioned) between him
and Isagoras. The latter doubtless found sufficient support, in the existing
senate and public assembly, to prevent it from being carried without an actual
appeal to the people. His opposition to it, moreover, is not
difficult to understand; for necessary as the change had become, it was not
the less a shock to ancient Attic ideas. It radically altered the very idea of
a tribe, which now became an aggregation of demes, of gentes—of fellow-demots, not of fellow-gentiles. It thus broke up those associations,
religious, social, and political, between the whole and the parts of the old
system, which operated powerfully on the mind of every old-fashioned Athenian.
The patricians at Rome who composed the gentes and curiae—and the plebs, who had no part in these corporations—formed
for a long time two separate and opposing fractions in the same city, each with its own separate organization. Only by slow degrees
did the plebs gain ground, while the political value of the patrician gens was
long maintained alongside of and apart from the plebeian tribe. So. too, in the
Italian and German cities of the middle ages, the patrician families refused to
part with their own separate political identity when the guilds grew up by the
side of them; even though forced to renounce a portion of their power, they
continued to be a separate fraternity, and would not submit to be regimented
anew, under an altered category and denomination, along with the traders who
had grown into wealth and importance. But the reform of Cleisthenes effected
this change all at once, both as to the name and as to the reality. In some
cases, indeed, that which had been the name of a gens was retained as the name
of a deme, but even then the old gentiles were ranked indiscriminately among
the remaining demots. The Athenian people, politely
considered, thus became one homogeneous whole distributed for convenience into
parts, numerical, local, and politically equal. It is, however, to be
remembered, that while the four Ionic tribes were abolished, the gentes and phratries which composed them were
left untouched, continuing to subsist as family and religious associations,
though carrying with them no political privilege.
The
ten newly-created tribes, arranged in an established order of precedence, were
called—Erechtheis, Aegeis, Pandionis, Leontis, Akamantis, Oeneis, Kekropis, Hippothoontis, Aeantis, Antiochis; names
borrowed chiefly from the respected heroes of Attic legend. This number
remained unaltered until the year 305 b.c., when it was increased to twelve by the addition of two new
tribes, Antigonias and Demetrias, afterward
designated anew by the names of Ptolemais and Attalis:
the mere names of these last two, borrowed from living kings, and not from
legendary heroes, betray the change from freedom to subservience at Athens.
Each tribe comprised a certain number of demes—cantons, parishes, or
townships—in Attica. But the total number of these demes is not distinctly
ascertained; for though we know that in the time of Polemo (the third century B.c.) it was 174, we cannot be
sure that it had always remained the same; and several critics construe the
words of Herodotus to imply that Cleisthenes at first recognized exactly one
hundred demes, distributed in equal proportion among his ten tribes. Such construction
of the words, however, is more than doubtful, while the fact itself is
improbable; partly because if the change of number had been so considerable as
the difference between one hundred and 174, some positive evidence of it would
probably be found—partly because Cleisthenes would indeed have a motive to
render the amount of citizen population nearly equal, but no motive to render
the number of demes equal, in each of the ten tribes. It is well known how
great is the force of local habits, and how unalterable are parochial or
cantonal boundaries. In the absence of proof to the contrary, therefore, we may
reasonably suppose the number and circumscription of the demes, as found or
modified by Cleisthenes, to have subsisted afterward with little alteration, at
least until the increase in the number of the tribes.
There
is another point, however, which is at once more certain and more important to
notice. The demes which Cleisthenes assigned to each tribe were in no case all
adjacent to each other; and therefore the tribe, as a whole, did not correspond
with any continuous portion of the territory, nor could it have any peculiar
local interest, separate from the entire community. Such systematic avoidance
of the factions arising out of neighborhood will appear to have been more
especially necessary when we recollect that the quarrels of the Parali, the Diakrii, the Pediaki, during the
preceding century, had all been generated from local feud, though doubtless
artfully fomented by individual ambition. Moreover, it was only by this same
precaution that the local predominance of the city, and the formation of a
city-interest distinct from that of the country, was obviated; which could
hardly have failed to arise had the city by itself constituted either one deme
or one tribe. Cleisthenes distributed the city (or found it already
distributed) into several demes, and those demes among several tribes; while
Peiraeus and Phalerum, each constituting a separate deme, were also assigned to
different tribes; so that there were no local advantages either to bestow predominance,
or to create a struggle for predominance, of one tribe over the rest. Each deme
had its own local interests to watch over; but the tribe was a mere aggregate
of demes for political, military, and religious purposes, with no separate
hopes or fears apart from the whole state. Each tribe had a chapel, sacred
rites and festivals, and a common fund for such meetings, in honor of its
eponymous hero, administered by members of its own choice: and the statues of
all the ten eponymous heroes, fraternal patrons of the democracy, were planted
in the most conspicuous part of the agora of Athens. In the future working of
the Athenian government, we shall trace no symptom of disquieting local
factions—a capital amendment, compared with the disputes of the preceding
century, and traceable in part to the absence of border-relations between demes
of the same tribe.
FUNCTIONS
OF THE DEME.
The
deme now became the primitive constituent element of the commonwealth, both as
to persons and as to property. It had its own demarch, its register of enrolled
citizens, is collective property, its public meetings and religious ceremonies,
its taxes levied and administered by itself. The register of qualified citizens
was kept by the demarch, and the inscription of new citizens took place at the
assembly of the demots, whose legitimate sons were
enrolled on attaining the age of eighteen, and their adopted sons at any time
when presented and sworn to by the adopting citizen. The citizenship could
only be granted by a public vote of the people, but wealthy non-free-men were
enabled sometimes to evade this law and purchase admission upon the register
of some poor deme, probably by means of a fictitious adoption. At the meetings
of the demots, the register was called over, and it
sometimes happened that some names were expunged, in which case the party thus
disfranchised had an appeal to the popular judicature. So great was the local
administrative power, however, of these demes, that they are described as the
substitute, under the Cleisthenean system, for the Naukraries under the Solonian and ante-Solonian. The Trittyes and Naukraries, though nominally preserved, and the
latter augmented in number from forty-eight to fifty, appear henceforward as
of little public importance.
Cleisthenes
preserved, but at the same time modified and expanded, all the main features of
Solon’s political constitution; the public assembly or Ekklesia—the preconsidering senate composed of members from all
the tribes—and the habit of annual election, as well as annual responsibility
of magistrates, by and to the Ekklesia. The full
value must now have been felt of possessing such pre-existing institutions to
build upon, at a moment of perplexity and dissension. But the Cleisthenean Ekklesia acquired new strength, and almost a new character,
from the great increase of the number of citizens qualified to attend it; while
the annually changed senate, instead of being composed of four hundred members
taken in equal proportion from each of the old four tribes, was enlarged to
five hundred, taken equally from each of the new ten tribes. It now comes
before us, under the name of Senate of Five Hundred, as an active and indispensable
body throughout the whole Athenian democracy: moreover the practice now seems
to have begun (though the period of commencement cannot be decisively proved)
of determining the names of the senators by lot. Both the senate thus
constituted, and the public assembly, were far more popular and vigorous than
they had been under the original arrangement of Solon.
The
new constitution of the tribes, as it led to a change in the annual senate, so
it transformed no less directly the military arrangements of the state, both
as to soldiers and as to officers. The citizens called upon to serve in arms
were now marshalled according to tribes—each tribe having its own taxiarchs as officers for the hoplites, and its own
phylarch at the head of the horsemen. Moreover, there were now
created, for the first time, ten strategi or generals, one
from each tribe; and two hipparchs,
for the supreme command of the horsemen. Under the prior Athenian
constitution it appears that the command of the military force
had been vested in the third archon or polemarch, no strategi then existing.
Even after the strategi had been created, under the Cleisthenean
constitution, the polemarch still retained a joint right of
command along with them—as we are told at the battle of Marathon, where Callimachus
the polemarch not only enjoyed an equal vote in
the council of war along with the ten strategi, but even occupied the post of
honor on the right wing. The ten generals annually changed are thus (like the
ten tribes) a fruit of the Cleisthenean constitution, which was at the same
time powerfully strengthened and protected by this remodeling of the military
force. The functions of the generals became more extensive as the democracy
advanced, so that they seem to have acquired gradually not
merely the direction of military and naval affairs, but also that of the foreign relations of the city generally—while
the nine archons, including the polemarch, were by degrees lowered down from
that full executive and judicial competence which they had once enjoyed, to the
simple ministry of police and preparatory justice. Encroached upon by the
strategi on one side, they were also restricted in efficiency, on the other
side, by the rise of the popular dikasteries or numerous jury-courts. We may be sure that these popular dikasteries had not been permitted to meet or to act under the despotism of the Peisistratids, and that the judicial business of the city
must then have been conducted partly by the senate of
Areopagus, partly by the archons; perhaps with
a nominal responsibility of the latter at the end of their year of office, to
an acquiescent Ekklesia. And if we even assume it to
be true, as some writers contend, that the habit of direct popular judicature
(over and above this annual trial of responsibility) had been partially
introduced by Solon, it must have been discontinued during the long coercion
exercised by the supervening dynasty. But the outburst of popular spirit,
which lent force to Cleisthenes, doubtless carried the people into direct
action as jurors in the aggregate Heliaea, not
less than as voters in the Ekklesia —and the change
was thus begun which contributed to degrade the archons from their primitive character as judges, into the lower function of
preliminary examiners and presidents of a jury. Such convocation of numerous
juries, beginning first with the aggregate body of sworn citizens
above thirty years of age, and subsequently dividing them into separate bodies
or panels for trying particular causes, became gradually more frequent and more
systematized; until at length, in the time of Pericles,
it was made to carry a small pay, and stood out as one
of the most prominent features of Athenian life. We cannot particularize the
different steps whereby such final development was attained,
and whereby the judicial competence of the archon was cut
down to the mere power of inflicting a small fine. But
the first steps of it are found in the revolution of Cleisthenes, and it seems
to have been consummated after the battle of Plataea. Of the function exercised
by the nine archons, as well as by many other magistrates and official persons
at Athens, in convoking a dikastery or jury-court, bringing on causes for
trial, and presiding over the trial—a function constituting one of the marks of
superior magistracy, and called the Hegemony or presidency of a dikastery—I
shall speak more at length hereafter. At present I wish merely to bring to view
the increased and increasing sphere of action on which the people entered at
the memorable turn of affairs now before us.
The
financial affairs of the city underwent at this epoch as complete a change as
the military. The appointment of magistrates and officers by tens, one from
each tribe, seems to have become the ordinary practice. A board of ten, called Apodektae, were invested with the supreme
management of the exchequer, dealing with the contractors as to those portions
of the revenue which were farmed, receiving all the taxes from the collectors,
and disbursing them under competent authority. Of this board the first
nomination is expressly ascribed to Cleisthenes as a substitute for certain
persons called Kolakretae, who had performed
the same function before and who were now retained only for subordinate
services. The duties of the Apodektae were
afterward limited to receiving the public income, and paying it over to the ten
treasurers of the goddess Athene, by whom it was kept in the inner chamber of
the Parthenon, and disbursed as needed; but this more complicated arrangement
cannot be referred to Cleisthenes. From his time forward too, the Senate of
Five Hundred steps far beyond its original duty of preparing matters for the
discussion of the Ekklesia. It embraces, besides, a
large circle of administrative and general superintendence, which hardly
admits of any definition. Its sittings become constant, with the exception of
special holidays. The year is distributed into ten portions called
Prytanies—the fifty senators of each tribe taking by turns the duty of constant
attendance during one prytany, and receiving
during that time the title of The Prytanes: the order of precedence
among the tribes in these duties was annually determined by lot. In the
ordinary Attic year of twelve lunar months, or 354 days, six of the prytanies contained thirty-five days, four of them
contained thirty-six: in the intercalated years of thirteen months, the number
of days was thirty-eight and thirty-nine respectively, Moreover a farther
subdivision of the prytany into five periods
of seven days each, and of the fifty tribe-senators into five bodies of ten
each, was recognized. Each body of ten presided in the senate for one period of
seven days, drawing lots every day among their number for a new chairman called Epistates, to whom during his day of office were confided the keys of
the acropolis and the treasury, together with the city seal. The remaining
senators, not belonging to the prytanising tribe,
might of course attend if they chose. But the attendance of nine among them,
one from each of the remaining nine tribes, was imperatively necessary to
constitute a valid meeting, and to insure a constant representation of the
collective people.
During
those later times known to us through the great orators, the Ekklesia, or formal assembly of the citizens, was
convoked four times regularly during each prytany,
or oftener if necessity required—usually by the senate, though the strategi had also the power of convoking it by their own authority. It was presided
over by the prytanes, and questions were put to the vote by their Epistates or
chairman. But the nine representatives of the non-prytanising tribes were always present, as a matter of course, and seem indeed in the days
of the orators to have acquired to themselves the direction of it, together
with the right of putting questions for the vote—setting aside wholly or
partially the fifty prytanes. When we carry our attention back, however, to the
state of the Ekklesia, as first organized by Cleisthenes
(I have already remarked that expositors of the Athenian constitution are too
apt to neglect the distinction of times, and to suppose that what was the
practice between 400-330 b.c. had been always the practice), it will appear probable that be provided one
regular meeting in each prytany, and no more; giving
to the senate and the strategi power of convening special meetings if needful
but establishing one Ekklesia during each prytany, or ten in the year, as a regular necessity of
state. How often the ancient Ekklesia had been
convoked during the interval between Solon and Peisistratus, we cannot exactly
say—probably but seldom during the year. Under the Peisistratids,
its convocation had dwindled down into an inoperative formality. Hence the
re-establishment of it by Cleisthenes, not merely with plenary determining powers,
but also under full notice and preparation of matters beforehand, together with
the best securities for orderly procedure, was in itself a revolution
impressive to the mind of every Athenian citizen. To render the Ekklesia efficient, it was indispensable that its meetings
should be both frequent and free. Men were thus trained to the duty both of
speakers and hearers, and each man, while he felt that he exercised his share
of influence on the decision, identified his own safety and happiness with the vote
of the majority, and became familiarized with the notion of a sovereign
authority which he neither could nor ought to resist. This was an idea new to
the Athenian bosom. With it came the feelings sanctifying free speech and
equal law—words which no Athenian citizen ever afterward heard unmoved,
together with that sentiment of the entire commonwealth as one indivisible,
which always overruled, though it did not supplant, the local and cantonal
specialties. It is not too much to say that these patriotic and ennobling
impulses were a new product in the Athenian mind, to which nothing analogous
occurs even in the time of Solon. They were kindled in part doubtless by the
strong reaction against the Peisistratids, but still
more by the fact that the opposing leader, Cleisthenes, turned
that transitory feeling to the best possible account, and gave to it a vigorous
perpetuity, as well as a well-defined positive object, by the popular elements
conspicuous in his constitution. His name makes less figure in history than we
should expect, because he passed for the mere renovator of Solon’s scheme of
government after it had been overthrown by Peisistratus. Probably he himself
professed this object, since it would facilitate the success of his
propositions: and if we confine ourselves to the letter of the case, the fact
is in a great measure true, since the annual senate and the Ekklesia are both Solonian—but both of them under his reform were clothed in totally new
circumstances, and swelled into gigantic proportions. How vigorous was the
burst of Athenian enthusiasm, altering instantaneously the position of Athens
among the powers of Greece, we shall hear presently from the lips of Herodotus,
and shall find still more unequivocally marked in the facts of his history.
JUDICIAL
ATTRIBUTES OF THE PEOPLE.
But
it was not only the people formally installed in their Ekklesia,
who received from Cleisthenes the real attributes of sovereignty—it was by him
also that the people were first called into direct action as dikasts, or jurors. I have already remarked
that this custom maybe said, in a certain limited sense, to have begun in the
time of Solon, since that lawgiver invested the popular assembly with the power
of pronouncing the judgment of accountability upon the archons after their year
of office. Here again the building, afterward so spacious and stately, was
erected on a Solonian foundation, though it was not itself Solonian. That the
popular dikasteries, in the elaborate form in which
they existed from Pericles downward, were introduced all at once by Cleisthenes,
it is impossible to belive. Yet the steps by which
they were gradually wrought out are not distinctly discoverable. It would
rather seem that at first only the aggregate body of citizens above thirty
years of age exercised judicial functions, being specially convoked and sworn
to try persons accused of public crimes, and when so employed bearing the name
of the Heliaea, or Heliasts;
private offenses and disputes between man and man being still determined by individual
magistrates in the city, and a considerable judicial power still residing in
the Senate of Areopagus. There is reason to believe that this was the state of
things established by Cleisthenes, which afterward came to be altered by the
greater extent of judicial duty gradually accruing to the Heliasts,
so that it was necessary to subdivide the collective Heliaea.
According
to the subdivision, as practiced in the times best known, 6,000 citizens above
thirty years of age were annually selected by lot out of the whole number, 600
from each of the ten tribes: 5,000 of these citizens were arranged in ten
panels or decuries of 500 each, the remaining 1000 being reserved to fill up
vacancies in case of death or absence among the former. The whole 6,000 took a
prescribed oath, couched in very striking words; after which every man received a
ticket inscribed with his own name as well as with a letter designating his
decury. When there were causes or crimes ripe for trial, the Thesmothets or six inferior archons determined by
lot, first, which decuries should sit, according to the number wanted—next, in
which court, or under the presidency of what magistrate, the decury B or E
should sit, so that it could not be known beforehand in what cause each would
be judge. In the number of persons who actually attended and sat, however,
there seems to have been much variety, and sometimes two decuries sat together.
The arrangement here described, we must recollect, is given to us as belonging
to those times when the dikasts received a regular
pay, after every day’s sitting; and it can hardly have long continued without
that condition, which was not realized before the time of Pericles. Each of
these decuries sitting in judicature was called the Heliaea—a
name which belongs properly to the collective assembly of the people; this collective
assembly having been itself the original judicature. I conceive that the
practice of distributing this collective assembly or Heliaea into sections of jurors for judicial duty, may have begun under one form or
another soon after the reform of Cleisthenes, since the direct interference of
the people in public affairs tended more and more to increase. But it could
only have been matured by degrees into that constant and systematic service
which the pay of Pericles called forth at last in completeness. Under the last
mentioned system the judicial competence of the archons was annulled, and the
third archon or polemarch withdrawn from all military functions. But this had
not been yet done at the time of the battle of Marathon, where Callimachus the
polemarch not only commanded along with the strategi, but enjoyed a sort of
pre-eminence over them; nor had it been done during the year after the battle
of Marathon, in which Aristides was archon—for the magisterial decisions of Aristides
formed one of the principal foundations of his honorable surname, the Just.
With
this question as to the comparative extent of judicial power vested by Cleisthenes
in the popular dikastery and the archons, are in reality connected two others
in Athenian constitutional law; relating first, to the admissibility of all
citizens for the post of archon—next, to the choosing of archons by lot. It is
well known that in the time of Pericles, the archons, and various other
individual functionaries, had come to be chosen by lot—moreover all citizens
were legally admissible, and might give in their names to be drawn for by lot,
subject to what was called the Dokimasy, or legal examination into their
status of citizen and into various moral and religious qualifications, before
they took office; while at the same time the function of the archon had become
nothing higher than preliminary examination of parties and witnesses for the
dikastery, and presidence over it when afterward
assembled, together with the power of imposing by authority a fine
of small amount upon inferior offenders. Now all these three political
arrangements hang essentially together. The great value of the lot, according
to Grecian democratic ideas, was that it equalized the chance of office between
rich and poor: but so long as the poor citizens were legally inadmissible,
choice by lot could have no recommendation either to the rich or to the poor.
In fact, it would be less democratic than election by the general mass of
citizens, because the poor citizen would under the latter system enjoy art
important right of interference by means of his suffrage, though he could not
be elected himself. Again, choice by lot could never under any circumstances be
applied to those posts where special competence, and a certain measure of
attributes possessed only by a few, were indispensable—nor was it ever applied
throughout the whole history of democratic Athens, to the strategi or generals,
who were always elected by show of hands of the assembled citizens. Accordingly,
we may regard it as certain, that at the time when the archons first came to be
chosen by lot, the superior and responsible duties once attached to that office
had been, or were in course of being, detached from it, and transferred either
to the popular dikasts or the ten elected strategi:
so that there remained to these archons only a routine of police and
administration, important indeed to the state, yet such as could be executed by
any citizen of average probity, diligence, and capacity—at least there was no
obvious absurdity in thinking so; while the Dokimasy excluded from the office
men of notoriously discreditable life, even after they might have drawn the
successful lot. Pericles, though chosen strategus year after year successively,
was never archon; and it may be doubted whether men of first-rate talents and
ambition often gave in their names for the office. To those of smaller
aspirations it was doubtless a source of importance, but it imposed troublesome
labor, gave no pay, and entailed a certain degree of peril upon any archon who
might have given offense to powerful men, when he came to pass through the
trial of accountability which followed immediately upon his year of office.
There was little to make the office acceptable, either to very poor men, or to
very rich and ambitious men; and between the middling persons who gave in their
names, any one might be taken without great practical mischief, always assuming
the two guarantees of the Dokimasy before, and accountability after office.
This was the conclusion—in my opinion a mistaken conclusion, and such as would
find no favor at present—to which the democrats of Athens were conducted by
their strenuous desire to equalize the chances of office for rich and poor. But
their sentiment seems to have been satisfied by a partial enforcement of the
lot to the choice of some offices— especially the archons, as the primitive
chief magistrates of the state —without applying it to all or to the most
responsible and difficult. Hardly would they have applied it to the archons, if
it had been indispensably necessary that these magistrates should retain
their original very serious duty of judging, disputes and condemning offenders.
I
think, therefore, that these three points—1. The opening of the post of archon
to all citizens indiscriminately; 2. The choice of archons by lot; 3. The
diminished range of the archon’s duties and responsibilities, through the
extension of those belonging to the popular courts of justice on the one hand
and to the strategi on the other—are all connected together, and must have been
simultaneous, or nearly simultaneous, in the time of introduction: the
enactment of universal admissibility to office certainly not coming after the
other two, and probably coming a little before them.
Now
in regard to the eligibility of all Athenians indiscriminately to the office of
archon, we find a clear and positive testimony as to the time when it was first
introduced. Plutarch tells us that the oligarchic, but high-principled, Aristides
was himself the proposer of this constitutional change, shortly after the battle
of Plataea, with the consequent expulsion of the Persians from Greece, and the
return of the refugee Athenians to their ruined city. Seldom has it happened
in the history of mankind that rich and poor have been so completely equalized
as among the population of Athens in that memorable expatriation and heroic
struggle; nor are we at all surprised to hear that the mass of the citizens,
coming back with freshly kindled patriotism as well as with the consciousness
that their country had only been recovered by the equal efforts of all, would
no longer submit to be legally disqualified from any office of state. It was on
this occasion that the constitution was first made really “common” to all, and
that the archons, strategi, and all functionaries, first began to be chosen
from all Athenians without any difference of legal eligibility. No mention is
made of the lot, in this important statement of Plutarch, which appears to me
everyway worthy of credit, and which teaches us, that down to the invasion of Xerxes,
not only had the exclusive principle of the Solonian law of qualification
continued in force (whereby the first three classes on the census were alone
admitted to all individual offices, and the fourth or Thetic class excluded),
but also the archons had hitherto been elected by the citizens—not taken by
lot. Now for financial purposes, the quadruple census of Solon was retained
long after this period, even beyond the Peloponnesian war and the oligarchy of
Thirty; but we thus learn that Cleisthenes in his constitution retained it for
political purposes also, in part at least. He recognized the exclusion of the
great mass of the citizens from all individual offices—such as the archon, the
strategus, etc. In his time, probably, no complaints were raised on the
subject. For his constitution gave to the collective bodies—senate, ekklesia, and heliaea or
dikastery—a degree of power and importance such as they had never before known
or imagined. And we may well suppose that the Athenian
people of that day had no objection
even to the proclaimed system and theory
of being exclusively governed by men of wealth
and station as individual magistrates—especially since many of
the newly enfranchised citizens had been before metics and slaves. Indeed it is to be added,
that even under the full democracy of later Athens,
though the people had then become passionately attached to the
theory of equal admissibility of all citizens to
office, yet in practice, poor men seldom
obtained offices which were elected by the general
vote, as will appear more fully in the
course of this history.
The
choice of the strategi remained ever afterward upon the footing
on which Aristides thus placed it; but the lot for the choice of archon
must have been introduced shortly after his proposition of universal eligibility, and in consequence
too of the same tide of democratic feeling—introduced
as a farther corrective, because the poor citizen,
though he had become eligible, was nevertheless not elected. And
at the same time, I imagine,
that elaborate distribution of the Heliaea, or aggregate body of dikasts or
jurors, into separate panels or dikasteries for
the decision of judicial matters, was first regularized. It
was this change that stole away from the archons so important a part
of their previous jurisdiction: it was this change that Pericles more
fully consummated by insuring pay to the dikasts.
But the present is not the time
to enter into the modifications which Athens underwent during
the generation after the battle of Plataea. They have
been here briefly noticed for the purpose of reasoning back, in
the absence of direct evidence, to Athens, as it stood in the generation
before that memorable battle, after the reform of Cleisthenes. His
reform, though highly democratical, stopped short of the mature democracy
which prevailed from Pericles to Demosthenes, in three ways
especially, among various others; and it is therefore sometimes considered
by the later writers as an aristocratical constitution:—1. It
still recognized the archons as
judges to a considerable extent, and the third archon
or polemarch as joint military commander along with the strategi.
2 It retained them as elected annually by the body of citizens,
not as chosen by lot. 3. It still excluded the fourth class of the
Solonian census from all individual
office, the archonship among the rest. The Solonian
law of exclusion, however, though retained in
principle, was mitigated in practice thus far—that whereas Solon had rendered none but members of the highest class on the census (the Pentakosiomedimni) eligible to the archonship, Cleisthenes
opened that dignity to all the first three classes,
shutting out only the fourth. That lie did this
may be inferred from the fact that Aristides, assuredly
not a rich man, became archon. I am
also inclined to believe that the senate of Five Hundred as constituted by Cleisthenes was taken,
not by election, but by lot,
from the ten tribes—and that every citizen became eligible
to it. Election for this purpose—that is, the privilege of
annually electing a batch of fifty senators all at once by each
tribe—would probably be thought more troublesome than valuable; nor do
we hear of separate meetings of each tribe for purposes of election. Moreover
the office of senator was a collective, not an individual office; the shock
therefore to the feelings of semi democratized Athens, from the unpleasant
idea of a poor man sitting among the fifty prytanes, would be less than if they
conceived him as polemarch at the head of the right wing of the army, or as an
archon administering justice.
A
farther difference between the constitution of Solon and that of Cleisthenes is
to be found in the position of the senate of Areopagus. Under the former, that
senate had been the principal body in the state, and Solon had even enlarged
its powers; under the latter, it must have been treated at first as an enemy
and kept down. For as it was composed only of all the past archons, and as
during the preceding thirty years every archon had been a creature of the Peisistratids, the Areopagites collectively must have been
both hostile and odious to Cleisthenes and his partisans—perhaps a fraction of
its members might even retire into exile with Hippias. Its influence must have
been sensibly lessened by the change of party, until it came to be gradually
filled by fresh archons springing from the bosom of the Cleisthenean
constitution. Now during this important interval, the new-modeled senate of
Five Hundred and the popular assembly stepped into that ascendency which they
never afterward lost. From the time of Cleisthenes forward, the Areopagites
cease to be the chief and prominent power in the state. Yet they are still
considerable; and when the second fill of the democratical tide took place,
after the battle of Plataea, they became the focus of that which was then considered
as the party of oligarchical resistance. I have already remarked that the
archons during the intermediate time (about 509-477 b.c.) were all elected by the ekklesia,
not chosen by lot—and that the fourth or poorest and most numerous class on the
census were by law then ineligible; while election at Athens, even when every
citizen without exception was an elector and eligible, had a natural tendency
to fall upon men of wealth and station. We thus see how it happened that the
past archons, when united in the senate of Areopagus, infused into that body
the sympathies, prejudices, and interests of the richer classes. It was this
which brought them into conflict with the more democratical party headed by Pericles
and Ephialtes, in times when portions of the Cleisthenean constitution had come
to be discredited as too much imbued with oligarchy.
One
other remarkable institution, distinctly ascribed to Cleisthenes, yet remains
to be noticed—the ostracism; upon which 1 have already made some remarks in
touching upon the memorable Solonian proclamation against neutrality in a
sedition. It is hardly too much to say that without this protective process
none of the other institutions would have reach maturity.
WEAKNESS
OF THE PUBLIC FORCE.
By
the ostracism a citizen was banished without special accusation, trial, or
defense for a term of ten years—subsequently diminished to five.
His property was not taken away, nor his reputation tainted; so that the
penalty consisted solely in the banishment from his native city to some other
Greek city. As to reputation, the ostracism was a compliment rather than
otherwise; and so it was vividly felt to be, when, about ninety years after Cleisthenes,
the conspiracy between Nicias and Alcibiades fixed it upon Hyperbolus: the two
former had both recommended the taking of an ostracizing vote, each hoping to
cause the banishment of the other; but before the day arrived, they
accommodated their own quarrel. To fire off the safety-gun of the republic
against a person so little dangerous as Hyperbolus, was denounced as the
prostitution of a great political ceremony: “It was not against such men as him
(said the comic writer Plato) that the shell was intended to be used.” The
process of ostracism was carried into effect by writing upon a shell or
potsherd the name of the person whom a citizen thought it prudent for a time to
banish; which shell, when deposited in the proper vessel, counted for a vote
toward the sentence.
I
have already observed that all the governments of the Grecian cities, when we
compare them with that idea which a modern reader is apt to conceive of the
measure of force belonging to a government, were essentially weak—the good as
well as the bad, the democratical, the oligarchical, and the despotic. The
force in the hands of any government, to cope with conspirators or mutineers,
was extremely small, with the single exception of a despot surrounded with his
mercenary troop. Accordingly, no tolerably sustained conspiracy or usurper
could be put down except by direct aid of the people in support of the
government; which amounted to a dissolution, for the time, of constitutional
authority, and was pregnant with reactionary consequences such as no man could
foresee. To prevent powerful men from attempting usurpation was therefore of
the greatest possible moment. Now a despot or an oligarchy might exercise at
pleasure preventive means, much sharper than the ostracism, such as the
assassination of Cimon, mentioned in my last chapter as directed by the Peisistratids. At the very least, they might send away any
one, from whom they apprehended attack or danger, without incurring even so
much as the imputation of severity. But in a democracy, where arbitrary action
of the magistrate was the thing of all others most dreaded, and where fixed
laws, with trial and defense as preliminaries to punishment, were conceived by
the ordinary citizen as the guarantees of his personal security and as the
pride of his social condition—the creation of such an exceptional power
presented serious difficulty. If we transport ourselves to the times of Cleisthenes,
immediately after the expulsion of the Peisistratids,
when the working of the democratical machinery was as yet untried, we shall
find this difficulty at its maximum. But we shall also find the necessity of
vesting such a power somewhere, absolutely imperative. For the great Athenian
nobles had yet to learn the lesson of respect for any constitution.
Their past history had exhibited continual struggles between the armed factions
of Megacles, Lycurgus, and Peisistratus, put down after a time by the superior force
and alliances of the latter; and though Cleisthenes, the son of Megacles, might
be firmly disposed to renounce the example of his father and to act as the
faithful citizen of a fixed constitution, he would know but too well that the
sons of his father’s companions and rivals would follow out ambitious purposes
without any regard to the limits imposed by law, if ever they acquired
sufficient partisans to present a fair prospect of success. Moreover, when any
two candidates for power, with such reckless dispositions, came into a bitter
personal rivalry, the motives to each of them, arising as well out of fear as
out of ambition, to put down his opponent at any cost to the constitution,
might well become irresistible, unless some impartial and discerning
interference could arrest the strife in time. “If the Athenians were wise (Aristides
is reported to have said, in the height and peril of his parliamentary struggle
with Themistocles), they would cast both Themistokles and me into the barathrum.” And whoever reads the sad narrative of the Corcyrian
sedition, in the third book of Thucydides, together with the reflections of the
historian upon it, will trace the gradual exasperation of these party feuds,
beginning even under democratical forms, until at length they break down the
barriers of public as well as of private morality.
PURPOSE
OF THE OSTRACISM
Against
this chance of internal assailants Cleisthenes had to protect the democratical
constitution—first, by throwing impediments in their way and rendering it
difficult for them to procure the requisite support; next, by eliminating them
before any violent projects were ripe for execution To do either the one or the
other, it was necessary to provide such a constitution as would not only
conciliate the good will, but kindle the passionate attachment, of the mass of
citizens, insomuch that not even any considerable minority should be
deliberately inclined to alter it by force. It was necessary to create In the
multitude, and through them to force upon the leading ambitious men, that rare
and difficult sentiment which we may term a constitutional morality—a paramount
reverence for the forms of the constitution, enforcing obedience to the
authorities acting under and within those forms, yet combined with the habit of
open speech, of action subject only to definite legal control, and unrestrained
censure of those very authorities as to all their public acts—combined, too,
With a perfect confidence in the bosom of every citizen, amidst the bitterness
of party contest, that the forms of the constitution will be not less sacred in
the eyes of his opponents than in his own. This co-existence of freedom and
self-imposed restraint—of obedience to authority with unmeasured censure of the
persons exercising it—may be found in the aristocracy of England (since about
1688) as well as in the democracy of the American United States: and because we
are familiar with it, we are apt to suppose it a natural sentiment; though there
seem to be few sentiments more difficult to establish and diffuse among a
community, judging by the
experience of history. We may see how imperfectly
it exists at this day in the Swiss Cantons; while the
many violences of the first French revolution illustrate, among
various other lessons, the fatal
effects arising from its absence, even among a people
high in the scale of intelligence. Yet the diffusion of such constitutional morality, not merely <unong the majority of any community, but throughout the whole, is the indispensable condition of a government at once free and peaceable;
since even any powerful and obstinate
minority may render the working of free institutions impracticable, without being strong enough to conquer ascendancy for themselves. Nothing less than unanimity, or so overwhelming
a majority as to be tantamount to unanimity, on the cardinal
point of respecting constitutional forms, even by those who do
not wholly approve of them, can render the excitement of political passion bloodless, and yet expose all the authorities in the state to
the full license of pacific criticism.
At
the epoch of Cleisthenes, which by a remarkable coincidence is the
same as that of the regifuge at Rome, such constitutional morality, if
it existed anywhere else, had certainly no place at Athens; and the first creation of it in
any particular society must be esteemed an interesting historical
fact. By the spirit of his reforms,—equal, popular, and
comprehensive, far beyond the previous experience of Athenians —he secured the hearty
attachment of the body of citizens. But from the
first generation of leading men, under the nascent democracy, and with such precedents as they had
to look back upon, no self-imposed limits to
ambition could be expected. Accordingly, Cleisthenes
had to find the means of eliminating beforehand any
one about to transgress these limits, so as to escape the necessity
of putting him down afterward, with all that bloodshed and reaction, in the midst of which the free working of the constitution would be suspended at least, if not
irrevocably extinguished. To acquire such
influence as would render him dangerous under democratical
forms, a man must stand in evidence before the public, so
as to afford some reasonable means of judging of his character and
purposes. Now the security which Cleisthenes provided was to call in the positive
judgment of the citizens respecting his future promise
purely and simply, so that they might not remain too long
neutral between two formidable political rivals—pursuant in
a certain way to the Solonian proclamation against neutrality in a sedition, as I have already remarked in a former chapter. He incorporated in
the constitution itself the principle of privilegium (to employ the Roman phrase, which signifies not a
peculiar favor granted to anyone,
but a peculiar inconvenience imposed), yet only under circumstances solemn and well-defined, with full
notice and discussion beforehand, and by
the positive secret vote of a large proportion of the
citizens, “No law shall be made against any single citizen, without
the same being made against all Athenian citizens; unless it shall so seem good
to 6,000 citizens voting secretly.” Such was that general principle of the
constitution, under which the ostracism was a particular case. Before the vote
of ostracism could be taken, a case was to be made out in the senate and the
public assembly to justify it. In the sixth prytany of the year, these two bodies debated and determined whether the state of the
republic was menacing enough to call for such an exceptional measure. If they
decided in the affirmative, a day was named, the agora was railed round, with
ten entrances left for the citizens of each tribe, and ten separate casks or
vessels for depositing the suffrages, which consisted of a shell or a potsherd
with the name of the person written on it whom each citizen designed to banish.
At the end of the day the number of votes were summed up, and if 6,000 votes were
found to have been given against any one per. son, that person was ostracized;
if not, the ceremony ended in nothing. Ten days were allowed to him for
settling his affairs, after which he was required to depart from Attica for ten
years, but retained his property, and suffered no other penalty.
It
was not the maxim at Athens to escape the errors of the people, by calling in
the different errors, and the sinister interest besides, of an extra-popular or
privileged few. Nor was any third course open, since the principles of
representative government were not understood, nor indeed conveniently
applicable to very small communities. Beyond the judgment of the people (so the
Athenians felt), there was no appeal. Their grand study was to surround the
delivery of that judgment with the best securities for rectitude, and the best
preservatives against haste, passion, or private corruption. Whatever measure
of good government could not be obtained in that way, could not, in their
opinion, be obtained at all. I shall illustrate the Athenian proceedings on
this head more fully when I come to speak of the working of their mature
democracy. Meanwhile in respect to this grand protection of the nascent
democracy—the vote of ostracism—it will be found that the securities devised
by Cleisthenes, for making the sentence effectual against the really dangerous
man and against no one else, display not less foresight than patriotism. The
main object was, to render the voting an expression of deliberate public
feeling, as distinguished from mere factious antipathy. Now the large minimum
of votes required (one-fourth of the entire citizen population) went far to
insure this effect—the more so, since each vote, taken as it was in a secret manner,
counted unequivocally for the expression of a genuine and independent
sentiment, and could neither be coerced nor bought. Then again. Cleisthenes did
not permit the process of ostracizing to be opened against any one citizen
exclusively. If opened at all, every one without exception was exposed to the
sentence; so that the friends of Themistocles could not invoke it against Aristides,
nor those of the latter against the former, without exposing their own leader to
the same chance of exile. It was not likely to be
invoked at all, therefore, until exasperation had proceeded so far as to render both
parties insensible to this chance—the precise index of that growing internecive hostility which the ostracism prevented from coming to a head. Nor could it even
then be ratified, unless a case was
shown to convince the more neutral portion of the senate and the ekklesia; moreover, after all, the ekklesia did not itself ostracize, but a future day was named, and the whole body of the citizens were solemnly invited to vote. It was in this way that
security was taken not only for making the ostracism effectual
in protecting the constitution, but to hinder it from
being employed for any other purpose. We must recollect that it exercised its tutelary influence not merely
on those occasions when it was actually
employed, but by the mere knowledge that it might be employed, and by the restraining effect
which that knowledge produced on the conduct of the great men. Again, the ostracism, though essentially of an exceptional nature, was yet an
exception sanctified and limited by
the constitution itself; so that the
citizen, in giving his ostracizing vote, did not in any
way depart from the constitution or lose his
reverence for it. The issue placed
before him—“Is there any man whom you think
vitally dangerous to the state? if so,
whom?”—though vague, was yet raised directly and legally. Had there
been no ostracism, it might probably have been raised both
indirectly and illegally, on the
occasion of some special imputed crime of a
suspected political leader, when accused before a
court of justice—a perversion
involving all the mischief of the ostracism, without its protective benefits.
Care
was taken to divest the ostracism of all painful consequence except what was inseparable from exile. This is not
one of the least proofs of the wisdom with which it was devised. Most certainly
it never deprived the public of candidates for political influence; and
when we consider the small amount of individual evil which it inflicted—evil,
too, diminished in the cases of Cimon and Aristides, by
a reactionary sentiment which augmented their subsequent
popularity after return—two remarks
will be quite sufficient to offer it. the
way of justification. First, it completely produced its
intended effect; for the democracy grew up
from infancy to manhood without a single
attempt to overthrow it by force—a result
upon which no reflecting contemporary of Cleisthenes could have ventured to calculate.
Next, through such tranquil working of the democratical forms, a constitutional morality quite sufficiently complete was produced
among the leading Athenians, to enable
the people after a certain time to dispense
with that exceptional security which the
ostracism offered. To the nascent democracy,
it was absolutely indispensable; to the growing,
yet militant democracy it was salutary; but the full-grown
democracy both could and did stand without it. The ostracism
passed upon Hyperbolus, about ninety years after Cleisthenes, was the last occasion of its employment. And even this can hardly be considered as a serious
instance: it was a trick concerted between two distinguished Athenians (Nicias
and Alcibiades) to turn to their own political account a process already coming
to be antiquated. Nor would such a maneuver have been possible, if the
contemporary Athenian citizens had been penetrated with the same serious
feeling of the value of ostracism as a safeguard of democracy, as had been once
entertained by their fathers and grandfathers. Between Cleisthenes and
Hyperbolus, we hear of about ten different persons as having been banished by
ostracism: first of all, Hipparchus of the deme Cholargus,
the son of Charmus, a relative of the
recently-expelled Peisistratid despots; then Aristides,
Themistocles, Cimon, and Thucydides, son of Melesias,
all of them renowned political leaders: also Alcibiades and Megacles (the
paternal and maternal grandfathers of the distinguished Alcibiades), and
Kallias, belonging to another eminent family at Athens; lastly, Damon, the
preceptor of Pericles in poetry and music, and eminent for his acquisitions in
philosophy. In this last case comes out the vulgar side of humanity,
aristocratical as well as democratical; for with both, the process of
philosophy and the persons of philosophers are wont to be alike unpopular. Even
Cleisthenes himself is said to have been ostracized under his own law, and Xanthippus; but both upon authority too weak to trust.
Miltiades was not ostracized at all, but tried and punished for misconduct in
his command.
I
should hardly have said so much about this memorable and peculiar institution
of Cleisthenes, if the erroneous accusations against the Athenian democracy, of
envy, injustice, and ill-treatment of their superior men, had not been greatly
founded upon it, and if such
criticisms had not passed from ancient times to modern with little examination.
In monarchical governments, a pretender to the throne, numbering a certain
amount of supporters, is as a matter of course excluded from the country. The
Duke of Bordeaux cannot now reside in France—nor could Napoleon after 1815—nor
Charles Edward in England during the last century. No man treats this as any
extravagant injustice, yet it is the parallel of the ostracism— with a stronger case in favor of the latter, inasmuch as the
change from one regal dynasty to another does not of necessity overthrow all
the collateral institutions and securities of the country. Plutarch has
affirmed that the ostracism arose from the envy and jealousy inherent in a
democracy, and not from justifiable fears—an observation often repeated, yet
not the less demonstrably untrue. Not merely because ostracism so worked as
often to increase the influence of that political leader whose rival it
removed—but still more, because, if the fact had been as Plutarch says, this
institution would have continued as long as the democracy; whereas it finished
with the banishment of Hyperbolus, at a period when the
government was more decisively democratical than it had been in the time of Cleisthenes. It was, in truth, a product altogether of
fear and insecurity on the part both of the democracy
and its best friends—fear perfectly well grounded, and only appearing needless
because the precautions taken prevented attack. So soon as the diffusion of a
constitutional morality had placed the mass of the citizens above all serious
fear of an aggressive usurper, the ostracism was discontinued. And doubtless
the feeling that it might safely be dispensed with must have been strengthened
by the long ascendency of Pericles—by the spectacle of the greatest statesman
whom Athens ever produced, acting steadily within the limits of the
constitution; and by the ill-success of his two opponents, Cimon and
Thucydides—aided by numerous partisans, and by the great comic writers, at a
period when comedy was a power in the state such as it has never been before or
since—in their attempts to get him ostracized. They succeeded in fanning up the
ordinary antipathy of the citizens toward philosophers so far as to procure the
ostracism of his friend and teacher Damon; but Pericles himself (to repeat the
complaint of his bitter enemy the comic poet Cratinus)
“holds his head as high as if he carried the Odeion upon it, now that the shell has gone by”—i.e. now that he has escaped the
ostracism. If Pericles was not conceived to be dangerous to the constitution,
none of his successors were at all likely to be so regarded. Damon and
Hyperbolus were the two last persons ostracized. Both of them were cases, and
the only cases, of an unequivocal abuse of the institution, because, whatever
the grounds of displeasure against them may have been, it is impossible to
conceive cither of them as menacing to the state—whereas all the other known
sufferers were men of such position and power, that the 6,000 citizens who
inscribed each name on the shell, or at least a large proportion of them, may
well have done so under the most conscientious belief that they were guarding
the constitution against real danger. Such a change in the character of the
persons ostracized plainly evinces that the ostracism had become dissevered
from that genuine patriotic prudence which originally rendered it both
legitimate and popular. It had served for two generations an inestimable
tutelary purpose—it lived to be twice dishonored—and then passed, by universal
acquiescence, into matter of history.
A
process analogous to the ostracism subsisted at Argos, at Syracuse, and in
some other Grecian democracies. Aristotle states that it was abused for
factious purposes: and at Syracuse, where it was introduced after the expulsion
of the Gelonian dynasty, Diodorus affirms that it was
so unjustly and profusely applied as to deter persons of wealth and station
from taking any part in public affairs for which reason it was speedily
discontinued. We have no particulars to enable us to appreciate this general
statement. But we cannot safely infer that because the ostracism worked on the
whole well at Athens, it must necessarily have worked well in other states—the
more so as we do not know whether it was surrounded with the same precautionary
formalities, nor whether it even required the same large
minimum of votes to make it effective. This latter guarantee, so valuable in
regard to an institution essentially easy to abuse, is nor noticed by Diodorus
in his brief account of the Petalism—so the process
was denominated at Syracuse.
Such
was the first Athenian democracy, engendered as well by the reaction against
Hippias and his dynasty as by the memorable partnership, whether spontaneous
or compulsory, between Cleisthenes and the unfranchised multitude. It is to be
distinguished both from the mitigated oligarchy established by Solon before,
and from the full-grown and symmetrical democracy which prevailed afterward
from the beginning of the Peloponnesian war, toward the close of the career of Pericles.
It was indeed a striking revolution, impressed upon the citizen not less by the
sentiments to which it appealed than by the visible change which it made in
political and social life. He saw himself marshaled in the ranks of hoplites
alongside of new companions in arms—he was enrolled in a new register, and his
property in a new schedule, in his deme and by his demarch, an officer before
unknown—he found the year distributed afresh, for all legal purposes, into ten
parts bearing the name of prytanies, each marked by a
solemn and free-spoken ekklesia at which he had a
right to be present—his ekklesia was convoked and presided
by senators called prytanes, members of a senate novel both as to number and
distribution—his political duties were now performed as member of a tribe,
designated by a name not before pronounced in common Attic life, connected with
one of ten heroes whose statues he now for the first time saw in the agora, and
associating him with fellow-tribemen from all parts
of Attica. All these and many others were sensible novelties felt in the daily
proceedings of the citizen. But the great novelty of all was the authentic
recognition of the ten new tribes as a sovereign Demos or people, apart from
all specialties of phratric or gentile origin, with
free speech and equal law; retaining no distinction except the four classes of
the Solonian property-schedule with their gradations of eligibility. To a
considerable proportion of citizens this great novelty was still farther
endeared by the fact that it had raised them out of the degraded position of metics and slaves; while to the large majority of all the
citizens, it furnished a splendid political idea, profoundly impressive to the
Greek mind—capable of calling forth the most ardent attachment as well as the
most devoted sense of active obligation and obedience. We have now, to see how
their newly-created patriotism manifested itself.
ISAGORAS
CALLS IN KLEOMENES.
Cleisthenes
and his new constitution carried with them so completely the popular favor,
that Isagoras had no other way of opposing it except by calling in the
interference of Cleomenes and the Lacedaemonians. Cleomenes listened the more
readily to this call, as he was reported to have been on an intimate footing
with the wife of Isagoras. He prepared to come to Athens; but his first aim was
to deprive the democracy of its great leader Cleisthenes, who, as belonging to
the Alkmaeonid family, was supposed to be tainted
with the inherited sin of his great-grandfather Megacles, the destroyer of the
usurper Kylon. Cleomenes sent a herald to Athens,
demanding the expulsion “of the accursed”—so this family were called by their
enemies, and so they continued to be called eighty years afterward, when the
same maneuver was practiced by the Lacedaemonians of that day against Pericles.
This requisition, recommended by Isagoras, was so well-timed, that Cleisthenes,
not venturing to disobey it, retired voluntarily; so that Cleomenes, though
arriving at Athens only with a small force, found himself master of the city.
At the instigation of Isagoras, he sent into exile 700 families, selected from
the chief partisans of Cleisthenes. His next attempt was to dissolve the new
senate of Five Hundred, and to place the whole government in the hands of 300
adherents of the chief whose cause he espoused. But now was seen the spirit
infused into the people by their new constitution. At the time of the first
usurpation of Peisistratus, the senate of that day had only not resisted, but
even lent themselves to the scheme. Now, the new senate of Cleisthenes
resolutely refused to submit to dissolution, while the citizens generally, even
after the banishment of the chief Cleisthenean partisans, manifested their
feelings in a way at once so hostile and so determined, that Cleomenes and
Isagoras were altogether baffled. They were compelled to retire into the
acropolis and stand upon the defensive. This symptom of weakness was the signal
for a general rising of the Athenians, who besieged the Spartan king on the
holy rock. He had evidently come without any expectation of finding, or any
means of overpowering, resistance; for at the end of two days his provisions
were exhausted, and he was forced to capitulate. He and his Lacedaemonians, as
well as Isagoras, were allowed to retire to Sparta; but the Athenians of the
party captured along with him were imprisoned, condemned, and executed by the
people.
Cleisthenes,
with the 700 exiled families, was immediately recalled, and his new
constitution materially strengthened by this first success. Yet the prospect of
renewed Spartan attack was sufficiently serious to induce him to send envoys
to Artaphernes, the Persian Satrap at Sardis, soliciting the admission of
Athens into the Persian alliance. He probably feared the intrigues of the
expelled Hippias in the same quarter. Artaphernes, having first informed
himself who the Athenians were, and where they dwelt, replied that if they
chose to send earth and water to the king of Persia they might be received as
allies, but upon no other condition. Such were the feelings of alarm under
which the envoys had quitted Athens, that they went the length of promising
this unqualified token of submission. But their countrymen on their return
disavowed them with scorn and indignation.
It
was at this time that the first connection began between Athens and the little
Boeotian town of Plataea, situated on the northern slope of
the range of Cithaeron, between that mountain and the river Asopus—on
the road from Athens to Thebes; and it is upon this occasion that we first
become acquainted with the Boeotians and their politics. In one of my preceding
volumes, the Boeotian federation has already been briefly described, as
composed of some twelve or thirteen autonomous towns under the headship of
Thebes, which was, or professed to have been, their mother-city. Plataea had
been (so the Thebans affirmed) their latest foundation; it was ill-used by
them, and discontented with the alliance. Accordingly, as Cleomenes was on his
way back from Athens, the Plataeans took the opportunity of addressing
themselves to him, craving the protection of Sparta against Thebes, and
surrendering their town and territory without reserve. The Spartan king, having
no motive to undertake a trust which promised nothing but trouble, advised them
to solicit the protection of Athens, as nearer and more accessible for them in
case of need. He foresaw that this would embroil the Athenians with Boeotia,
and such anticipation was in fact his chief motive for giving the advice, which
the Plataeans followed. Selecting an occasion of public sacrifice at Athens,
they dispatched thither envoys, who sat down as suppliants at the altar,
surrendered their town to Athens, and implored protection against Thebes. Such
an appeal was not to be resisted, and protection was promised. It was soon needed,
for the Thebans invaded the Plataean territory, and
an Athenian force marched to defend it, Battle was about to be joined, when the
Corinthians interposed with their mediation, which was accepted by both
parties. They decided altogether in favor of Plataea, pronouncing that the
Thebans had no right to employ force against any seceding member of the
Boeotian federation. The Thebans, finding the decision against them, refused to
abide by it, and attacked the Athenians on their return, but sustained a complete
defeat; a breach of faith which the Athenians avenged by joining to Plataea the
portion of Theban territory south of the Asopus, and
making that river the limit between the two. By such success, however, the
Athenians gained nothing, except the enmity of Boeotia—as Cleomenes had
foreseen. Their alliance with Plataea, long-continued, and presenting in the
course of this history several incidents touching to our sympathies, will be
found, if we except one splendid occasion, productive only of burden to the
one party, yet insufficient as a protection to the other.
Meanwhile
Cleomenes had returned to Sparta full of resentment against the Athenians, and
resolved on punishing them as well as on establishing his friend Isagoras as
despot over them. Having been taught, however, by humiliating experience, that
this was no easy achievement, he would not make the attempt, without having
assembled a considerable force. He summoned allies from all the various states
of Peloponnesus, yet without venturing to inform them what he was about to
undertake. He at the same time concerted measures
with the Boeotians, and with the Chalcidians of Euboea, for a simultaneous
invasion of Attica on all sides. It appears that he had greater confidence in their
hostile dispositions toward Athens than in those of the Peloponnesians, for he
was not afraid to acquaint them with his design—and probably the Boeotians were
incensed with the recent interference of Athens in the affair of Plataea. As
soon as these preparations were completed, the two kings of Sparta, Cleomenes
and Demaratus, put themselves at the head of the united Peloponnesian force,
marched into Attica, and advanced as far as Eleusis on the way to Athens. But
when the allies came to know the purpose for which they were to be employed, a
spirit of dissatisfaction manifested itself among them. They had no unfriendly
sentiment toward Athens; and the Corinthians especially, favorably disposed
rather than otherwise toward that city, resolved to proceed no farther,
withdrew their contingent from the camp, and returned home. At the same time,
King Demaratus, either sharing in the general dissatisfaction or moved by some
grudge against his colleague which had not before manifested itself, renounced
the undertaking also. Two such examples, operating upon the pre-existing
sentiment of the allies generally, caused the whole camp to break up and return
home without striking a blow.
We
may here remark that this is the first instance known in which Sparta appears
in act as recognized head of an obligatory Peloponnesian alliance, summoning
contingents from the cities to be placed under the command of her king. Her
headship, previously recognized in theory, passes now into act, but in an
unsatisfactory manner, so as to prove the necessity of precaution and concert
beforehand—which will be found not long wanting.
SUCCESSES
OF ATHENS.
Pursuant
to the scheme concerted, the Boeotians and Chalcidians attacked Attica at the
same time that Cleomenes entered it. The former seized Oenoe and Hysiae, the frontier demes of Attica on the side toward
Plataea; while the latter assailed the north-eastern frontier which faces
Euboea. Invaded on three sides, the Athenians were in serious danger, and were
compelled to concentrate all their forces at Eleusis against Cleomenes, leaving
the Boeotians and Chalcidians unopposed. But the unexpected breaking up of the
invading army from Peloponnesus proved their rescue, and enabled them to turn
the whole of their attention to the other frontier. They marched into Boeotia
to the strait called Euripus which separates it from Euboea intending to
prevent the junction of the Boeotians and Chalcidians, and to attack the latter
first apart. But the arrival of the Boeotians caused an alteration in their
scheme; they attacked the Boeotians first, and gained a victory of the most
complete character—killing a large number, and capturing 700 prisoners. On the
very same day they crossed over to Euboea, attacked the Chalcidians, and gained
another victory so decisive that it at once terminated the war. Many Chalcidians
were taken, as well as Boeotians, and conveyed in chains to
Athens, where after a certain detention they were at last ransomed for two minae per man. Of the sum thus raised, a
tenth was employed in the fabrication of a chariot and four horses in bronze,
which was placed in the acropolis to commemorate the victory. Herodotus saw
this trophy when he was at Athens. He saw, too, what was a still more speaking
trophy, the actual chains in which the prisoners had been fettered, exhibiting
in their appearance the damage undergone when the acropolis was burnt by
Xerxes: an inscription of four lines described the offerings and recorded the
victory out of which they had sprung.
Another
consequence of some moment arose out of this victory. The Athenians planted a
body of 4,000 of their citizens as Kleruchs (lot-holders) or settlers upon the lands of the wealthy Chalcidian oligarchy
called the Hippobotae—proprietors probably in
the fertile plain of Lelantum between Chalcis and
Eretria. This is a system which we shall find hereafter extensively followed
out by the Athenians in the days of their power; partly with the view of
providing for their poorer citizens—partly to serve as garrison among a population
either hostile or of doubtful fidelity. These Attic Kleruchs (I can find no other name by which to speak of them) did not lose their
birth-right as Athenian citizens. They were not colonists in the Grecian sense,
and they are known by a totally different name—but they correspond very nearly
to the colonies formerly planted out on the conquered lands by Rome. The
increase of the poorer population was always more or less painfully felt in
every Grecian city; for though the aggregate population never seems to have
increased very fast, yet the multiplication of children in poor families caused
the subdivision of the smaller lots of land, until at last they became
insufficient for a maintenance; and the persons thus impoverished found it difficult
to obtain subsistence in other ways, more especially as the labor for the
richer classes was so much performed by imported slaves. Doubtless some
families possessed of landed property became extinct. Yet this did not at all
benefit the smaller and poorer proprietors, for the lands rendered vacant
passed, not to them, but by inheritance or bequest or intermarriage to other
proprietors for the most part in easy circumstances—since one opulent family
usually intermarried with another. I shall enter more fully at a future
opportunity into this question—the great and serious problem of population, as
it affected the Greek communities generally, and as it was dealt with in theory
by the powerful minds of Plato and Aristotle—at present it is sufficient to
notice that the numerous Kleruchies sent out by
Athens, of which this to Euboea was the first, arose in a great measure out of
the multiplication of the poorer population, which her extended power was
employed in providing for. Her subsequent proceedings with a view to the same
object will not be always found so justifiable as this now before us, which
grew naturally, according to the ideas of the time, out of her success against
the Chalcidians.
The
war between Athens, however, and Thebes with her Boeotian allies, still
continued, to the great and repeated disadvantage of the latter, until at
length the Thebans in despair sent to ask advice
of the Delphian oracle, and were directed to
“solicit aid from those nearest to them.” “How (they replied) are we to obey? Our nearest neighbors, of Tanagra, Koroneia, and Thespiae, are
now, and have been from the beginning, lending us all the aid in their power.” An
ingenious Theban, however, coming to the relief of his perplexed
fellow-citizens, dived into the depths of legend
and brought up a happy meaning. “Those
nearest to us (he said) are the inhabitants
of Aegina: for Thebe (the eponym of Thebes) and Aegina (the eponym of
that island) were both sisters, daughters of Asopus. Let us send
to crave assistance from the Aeginetans.” If
his subtle interpretation (founded upon their descent
from the same legendary progenitors) did
not at once convince all who heard it, at least no one had any better to suggest. Envoys were
at once sent to the Aeginetans; who, in reply to a petition founded on
legendary claims, sent to the help of the Thebans a
reinforcement of legendary, but venerated,
auxiliaries— the Aeakid heroes. We are
left to suppose that their effigies are here meant. It was in vain, however,
that the glory and the supposed presence
of the Aeakids Telamon and Peleus
were introduced into the Theban camp. Victory still
continued on the side of Athens; so that the discouraged Thebans again sent
to Aegina, restoring the heroes, and praying for aid of a character more human and positive. Their
request was granted, and the Aeginetans commenced war
against Athens, without even the decent preliminary of
a herald and declaration.
This
remarkable embassy first brings us into acquaintance with
the Dorians of Aegina—oligarchical, wealthy, commercial, and powerful at sea, even
in the earliest days; more analogous to Corinth
than to any of the other cities called Dorian. The
hostility which they now began
without provocation against Athens—repressed
by Sparta at the critical moment of the battle
of Marathon—then again breaking out—and hushed for a
while by the common dangers of
the Persian invasion under Xerxes, was appeased only with the conquest of the island about twenty years after that event, and with the expulsion and destruction of its inhabitants. There had been indeed, according
to Herodotus, a feud of great antiquity between Athens and Aegina—of
which he gives the account in a singular narrative blending together
religion, politics, exposition of ancient
customs, etc. But at the time when the Thebans solicited
aid from Aegina, the latter was at peace with Athens. The Aeginetans employed their fleet,
powerful for that day, in ravaging Phalerum and the maritime demes of Attica; nor had the Athenians as yet any fleet to resist them.
It is probable that the desired effect was produced, of diverting a portion of
the Athenian force from the war against Boeotia, and thus partially relieving
Thebes; but the war of Athens against both of them continued for a considerable
time, though we have no information respecting its details.
Meanwhile
the attention of Athens was called off from these combined enemies by a more
menacing cloud which threatened to burst upon her from the side of Sparta. Cleomenes
and his countrymen, full of resentment at the late inglorious desertion of
Eleusis, were yet more incensed by the discovery, which appears to have been
then recently made, that the injunctions of the Delphian priestess for the
expulsion of Hippias from Athens had been fraudulently pro cured. Moreover Cleomenes,
when shut up in the acropolis of Athens with Isagoras, had found there various
prophecies previously treasured up by the Peisistratids,
many of which foreshadowed events highly disastrous to Sparta. And while the
recent brilliant manifestations of courage and repeated victories, on the part
of Athens, seemed to indicate that such prophecies might perhaps be
realized—Sparta bad to reproach herself, that, from the foolish and mischievous
conduct of Cleomenes, she had undone the effect of her previous aid against the Peisistratids, and thus lost that return of gratitude
which the Athenians would otherwise have testified. Under such impressions,
the Spartan authorities took the remarkable step of sending for Hippias from
his residence at Sigeium to Peloponnesus, and of
summoning deputies from all their allies to meet him at Sparta.
The
convocation thus summoned deserves notice as the commencement of a new era in
Grecian politics. The previous expedition of Cleomenes against Attica presents
to us the first known example of Spartan headship passing from theory into act:
that expedition miscarried because the allies, though willing to follow, would
not follow blindly, nor be made the instruments of executing purposes repugnant
to their feelings. Sparta had now learnt the necessity, in order to insure
their hearty concurrence, of letting them know what she contemplated, so as to
ascertain at least that she had no decided opposition to apprehend. Here then
is the third stage in the spontaneous movement of Greece toward a systematic
conjunction, however imperfect, of its many autonomous units; first we have
Spartan headship suggested in theory, from a concourse of circumstances which
attract to her the admiration of all Greece—power, unrivaled training,
undisturbed antiquity, etc.: next, the theory passes into act, yet rude and
shapeless: lastly, the act becomes clothed with formalities and preceded by
discussion and determination. The first convocation of the allies at Sparta,
for the purpose of having a common object submitted to their consideration, may
well be regarded as an important event in Grecian political history: the
proceedings at the convocation are no less important, as an indication of the
way in which the Greeks of that day felt and acted, and must be borne
in mind as a contrast with times hereafter to be described.
PROCEEDINGS
OF THE CONVOCATION
Hippias
having been presented to the assembled allies, the Spartans expressed their
sorrow for having dethroned him—their resentment and alarm at the newborn
insolence of Athens, already tasted by her immediate neighbors, and menacing to
every state represented in the convocation—and their anxiety to restore
Hippias, not less as a reparation of the past wrong, than as a means, through
his rule, of keeping Athens low and dependent. But the proposition, though
emanating from Sparta, was listened to by the allies with one common sentiment
of repugnance. They had no sympathy for Hippias—no dislike, still less any
fear, of Athens—and a profound detestation of the character of a despot. The
spirit which had animated the armed contingents at Eleusis now re-appeared
among the deputies at Sparta, and the Corinthians again took the initiative.
Their deputy Sosikles protested against the project
in the fiercest and most indignant strain. No language can be stronger than
that of the long harangue which Herodotus puts into his mouth, wherein the
bitter recollections prevalent at Corinth respecting Kypselus and Periander are poured forth. “Surely heaven and earth are about to change
places—the fish are coming to dwell on dry land, and mankind going to inhabit
the sea—when you, Spartans, propose to subvert the popular governments, and to
set up in the cities that wicked and bloody thing called a Despot. First try
what it is for yourselves at Sparta, and then force it upon others if you can:
you have not tasted its calamities as we have, and you take very good care to
keep it away from yourselves. We adjure you by the common gods of Hellas—plant
not despots in her cities: if you persist in a scheme so wicked, know that the
Corinthians will not second you.”
This
animated appeal was received with a shout of approbation and sympathy on the
part of the allies. All with one accord united with Sosikles in adjuring the Lacedaemonians “not to revolutionize any Hellenic city.” No one
listened to Hippias when he replied, and warned the Corinthians that the time
would come, when they, more than anyone else, would dread and abhor the
Athenian democracy, and wish the Peisistratidae back
again. “He knew well (says Herodotus) that this would be, for he was better
acquainted with the prophecies than any man; but no one then believed him, and
he was forced to take his departure back to Sigeium;
the spartans not venturing to espouse his cause
against the determined sentiment of the allies.”
That
determined sentiment deserves notice, because it marks the present period of
the Hellenic mind; fifty years later it will be found materially altered.
Aversion to single-headed rule, and bitter recollection of men like Kypselus and Periander, are now the chords which thrill in
an assembly of Grecian deputies. The idea of a revolution (implying thereby an
organic and comprehensive change of which the party using the
word disapproves) consists in substituting a permanent One in place of those
periodical magistrates and assemblies which were the common attribute of
oligarchy and democracy; the antithesis between these last two is as yet in the
background, and there prevails neither fear of Athens nor hatred of the
Athenian democracy. But when we turn to the period immediately before the
Peloponnesian war, we find the order of precedence between these two sentiments
reversed. The anti-monarchical feeling has not perished, but has been overlaid
by other and more recent political antipathies—the antithesis between democracy
and oligarchy having become, not indeed the only sentiment, but the uppermost
sentiment, in the minds of Grecian politicians generally, and the soul of
active party movement. Moreover, a hatred of the most deadly character has
grown up against Athens and her democracy, especially in the grandsons of
those very Corinthians who now stand forward as her sympathizing friends. The
remarkable change of feeling here mentioned is nowhere so strikingly exhibited
as when we contrast the address of the Corinthian Sosikles just narrated, with the speech of the Corinthian envoys at Sparta immediately
antecedent to the Peloponnesian war, as given to us in Thucydides. It will
hereafter be fully explained by the intermediate events, by the growth of
Athenian power, and by the still more miraculous development of Athenian
energy.
Such
development, the fruit of the fresh-planted democracy as well as the seed for
its sustentation and aggrandizement, continued progressive during the whole
period just adverted to; but the first unexpected burst of it, under the Kleisthenean constitution and after the expulsion of
Hippias is described by Herodotus in terms too emphatic to be omitted. After
narrating the successive victories of the Athenians over both Boeotians and Chalcidians,
that historian proceeds—“Thus did the Athenians grow in strength. And we may
find proof not merely in this instance but everywhere else, how valuable a
thing freedom is; since even the Athenians, while under a despot, were not
superior in war to any of their surrounding neighbors, but so soon as they got
rid of their despots, became by far the first of all. These things show that
while kept down by one man, they were slack and timid, like men working for a
master; but when they were liberated, every single man became eager in
exertions for his own benefit.” The same comparison reappears a short time
afterward, where he tells us that “the Athenians, when free, felt themselves
a match for Sparta; but while kept down by any man under a despotism, were
feeble and apt for submission.”
Stronger
expressions cannot be found to depict the rapid improvement wrought in the
Athenian people by their new democracy. Of course this did not arise merely
from suspension of previous cruelties, or from better laws, or better
administration. These, indeed, were essential conditions, but the active
transforming cause here was, the principle and system of which
such amendments formed the detail: the grand and new idea of the sovereign
people, composed of free and equal citizens—or liberty and equality, to use
words which so profoundly moved the French some centuries ago. It was this
comprehensive political idea which acted with electric effect upon the
Athenians, creating within them a host of sentiments, motives, sympathies, and
capacities, to which they had before been strangers. Democracy in Grecian
antiquity possessed the privilege, not only of kindling an earnest and
unanimous attachment to the constitution in the bosoms of the citizens, but
also of creating an energy of public and private action, such as could never be
obtained under an oligarchy, where the utmost that could be hoped for was a
passive acquiescence and obedience. Mr. Burke has remarked that the mass of the
people are generally very indifferent about theories of government; but such
indifference (although improvements in the practical working of all governments
tend to foster it) is hardly to be expected among any people who exhibit decided
mental activity and spirit on other matters; and the reverse was unquestionably
true, in the year 500 b.c., among the communities of ancient
Greece. Theories of government were there anything but a dead letter: they
were connected with emotions of the strongest as well as of the most opposite
character. The theory of a permanent ruling One, for example, was universally
odious: that of a ruling Few, though acquiesced in, was never positively
attractive, unless either where it was associated with the maintenance of
peculiar education and habits, as at Sparta, or where it presented itself as
the only antithesis to democracy, the latter having by peculiar circumstances
become an object of terror. But the theory of democracy was pre-eminently
seductive; creating in the mass of the citizens an intense positive attachment,
and disposing them to voluntary action and suffering on its behalf, such as no
coercion on the part of other governments could extort. Herodotus, in his
comparison of the three sorts of government, puts in the front rank of the
advantages of democracy “its most splendid name and promise”—its power of
enlisting the hearts of the citizens in support of their constitution, and of
providing for all a common bond of union and fraternity. This is what even
democracy did not always do; but it was what no other government in Greece
could do; a reason alone sufficient to stamp it as the best government, and presenting
the greatest chance of beneficent results, for a Grecian community. Among the
Athenian citizens, certainly, it produced a strength and unanimity of positive
political sentiment, such as has rarely been seen in the history of mankind,
which excites our surprise and admiral ion the more when we compare it with the
apathy which had preceded, and which is even implied as the natural state of
the public mind in Solon’s famous proclamation against neutrality in a
sedition. Because democracy happens to be unpalatable to most modern readers,
they have been accustomed to look upon the sentiment here described only in
its least honorable manifestations —in the caricatures of Aristophanes, or in
the empty commonplaces of rhetorical declaimers. But it is not in this way that
the force, the earnestness, or the binding value of democratic sentiment at
Athens is to be measured. We must listen to it as it comes from the lips of Pericles,
while he is strenuously enforcing upon the people those active duties for which
it both implanted the stimulus and supplied the courage; or from the oligarchic Nikiasin the harbor of Syracuse, when he is
endeavoring to revive the courage of his despairing troops for one last
death-struggle, and when he appeals to their democratic patriotism as to the
only flame yet alive and burning even in that moment of agony. From the time of
Cleisthenes downward, the creation of this new mighty impulse makes an entire
revolution in the Athenian character; and if the change still stood out in so
prominent a manner before the eyes of Herodotus, much more must it have been
felt by the contemporaries among whom it occurred.
The
attachment of an Athenian citizen to his democratic constitution comprised two
distinct veins of sentiment: first, his rights, protection, and advantages
derived from it—next, his obligations of exertion and sacrifice toward it and
with reference to it. Neither of these two veins of sentiment was ever wholly
absent; but according as the one or the other was present at different times in
varying pro portions, the patriotism of the citizen was a very different
feeling. That which Herodotus remarks is, the extraordinary efforts of heart
and hand which the Athenians suddenly displayed; the efficacy of the active
sentiment throughout the bulk of the citizens. We shall observe even more
memorable evidences of the same phenomenon in tracing down the history from Cleisthenes
to the end of the Peloponnesian war: we shall trace a series of events and
motives eminently calculated to stimulate that self-imposed labor and
discipline which the early democracy had first called forth. But when we
advance farther down, from the restoration of the democracy after the Thirty
Tyrants, to the time of Demosthenes—(I venture upon this brief anticipation,
in the conviction that one period of Grecian history can only be thoroughly
understood by contrasting it with another)—we shall find a sensible change in
Athenian patriotism. The active sentiment of obligation is comparatively
inoperative; the citizen, it is true, has a keen sense of the value of the
democracy as protecting him and insuring to him valuable rights, and he is,
moreover, willing to perform his ordinary sphere of legal duties toward it; but
he looks upon it as a thing established, and capable of maintaining itself in a
due measure of foreign ascendency, without any such personal efforts as those
•which his forefathers cheerfully imposed upon themselves. The orations of
Demosthenes contain melancholy proofs of such altered tone of patriotism—of
that langour, paralysis, and waiting for others to
act, which preceded the catastrophe of Chaeroneia,
notwithstanding an unabated attachment to the democracy as a source
of protection and good government. That same preternatural activity which the
allies of Sparta, at the beginning of the Peloponnesian war, both denounced
and admired in the Athenians, is noted by the orator as now belonging to their
enemy Philip. Such variations in the scale of national energy pervade history,
modern as well as ancient, but in regard to Grecian history, especially, they
can never be overlooked. For a certain measure, not only of positive political
attachment, but also of active self-devotion, military readiness, and personal
effort, was the indispensable condition of maintaining Hellenic autonomy,
either in Athens or elsewhere; and became so more than ever when the
Macedonians were once organized under an enterprising and semi-Hellenized
prince. The democracy was the first creative cause of that astonishing personal
and many-sided energy which marked the Athenian character, for a century
downward from Cleisthenes; that the same ultra-Hellenic activity did not longer
continue, is referable to other causes which will be
hereafter in part explained. No system of government, even supposing it to be
very much better and more faultless than the Athenian democracy, can ever
pretend to accomplish its legitimate end apart from the personal character of
the people, or to supersede the necessity of individual virtue and vigor.
During the half-century immediately preceding the battle of Chaeroneia,
the Athenians had lost that remarkable energy which distinguished them during
the first century of their democracy, and had fallen much more nearly to a
level with the other Greeks, in common with whom they were obliged to yield to
the pressure of a foreign enemy. I here briefly notice their last period of
languor, in contrast with the first burst of democratic fervor under Cleisthenes
now opening—a feeling, winch will be found, as we proceed, to continue for a
longer period than could have been reasonably anticipated, but which was too
high-strung to become a perpetual and inherent attribute of any community.
|